Monday, March 4, 2019

How to Write Book Review

How to write a pack got look into Perhaps the outdo way to offer guidelines on how to write a disk review is to give you an illustration of the mannikin of instructions and guidelines we (i. e. the academic staff) would be stipulation by journals who invite us to review intelligences for them. So, here ar the instructions given to sources by the ledger of Autism and Develop psychogenic Disorders. A book review should be an objective and discreet evaluation of a book. The review should offer logic and situation in support of its evaluations.With come in being just an abstract of the book, the review should indicate the personality and scope of the books content. It should indicate the goals of the compose, the techniques determinationd to achieve those goals, and the advantage of those techniques. You may also discuss how the book relates to its field and how it comp ares to former(a) books in the field. It is important for your review to discuss what audience the b ook or other media best serves and to state whether the reviewer recommends it.The review should attempt to place the book within a context (e. g. , Is this a new approach? unmatchable that builds on an earlier one? ). Reviews should attempt to convey a none of the book over all(prenominal) (i. e. , not just summarize the table of contents. Quotes (see on a lower floor AQ are in that location examples to be provided? ) tidy sum often help in this process. If you feel that the book does not merit a review in the Journal please let us know there is no requirement that we review every book received and it is perfectly grateful to do a negative review . nd here is an example of an actual review written by Dermot Bowler and published in the European Journal of Disorders of Communication (Volume 31, pp 210-213). Note, however, that this review is somewhat longer than your word-limit permits. essay REVIEW (reproduced with permission of the author) Review of Baron-Cohen, S. (1995) . Mindblindness An Essay on Autism and Theory of Mind. Cambridge, MA. MIT Press. The consolidation of a aim of theoretical perspectives to provide a coherent scientific account of a natural phenomenon is an easy task only for those who have never had to do it.In this volume, Simon Baron-Cohen has attempted such(prenominal) a difficult turn by integrating currently fashionable modularist cognitive science accounts of the tender dysfunction found in throng with autism into neuropsychological and evolutionary frameworks. In the first trinity Chapters of the book, he aims to persuade us firstly that the comment of the behaviour of other people using the mentalistic language of folk-psychology (John took his umbrella with him beca consumption he thought it efficacy rain) is both highly efficient and evolutionarily advantageous to a species such as ourselves that relies heavily on social nerve for survival.In Chapter 4, he generates a model of development which gutter account for the emergence of the skill to mindread in non-autistic children and, taking the well documented deficits in autism of omit of protodeclarative pointing, lack of symbolic play and the failure to understand that another person nooky act in accordance with a belief that the observer knows to be false, their failure to develop in children with autism. His account draws heavily on Fodors (1983) flavour that the mind is made up of independent domain-specific modules, the outputs of which interact to yield mental life and behaviour.He also develops earlier accounts such as that of Leslie and Roth (1993), which posit a specific modular mechanism that enables people to understand minds. Specifically, Baron-Cohen outlines four modular systems that are necessary for the process he calls mindreading. The first of these he scathe an intentionality seeor (ID) which is triggered by stimuli exhibiting self-propelled motion and computes desire- or goal-based dyadic representations. The se condment is the eye direction detector (EDD) which is fired by eye-like stimuli and generates representations of the contents of agents opthalmic fields.Mechanism number three is called the shared attention mechanism (surface-to-air missile) which takes input from IDD and ED to compute triadic representations of the kind Daddy sees I see the cat at the window. Finally, there is the theory of mind mechanism (ToMM), a term borrowed from Leslies work, which takes inputs from SAM and knowledge of mental states and their consequences which gutter be used in a hypothetico-deductive way by someone possessing a full theory of mind.I n Chapters 4 and 5 of the book, Baron-Cohen marshals a considerable body of cause in support of the existence of these modules and of their selective breakdown in autism. Briefly, he argues that ID and ED are functional in autism, although he acknowledges that there are still considerable gaps in the march. By contrast, SAM and ToMM are sternly impaired. In Chapter 6, he draws together order from neuropsychological and neurological studies on humans and other species to attempt to localise these modular systems in the judgement.In the terminal two Chapters, he develops the theme that the capacity to read minds depends crucially on the ability to decode information from the eyes of others, and returns to the theme that this capacity can best be understood within an evolutionary framework. As I said at the outset, Mindreading is a tour de force, in that it draws together evidence from a variety of fields with the aim of providing a coherent furnish of the phenomenon of how homo sapiens can account for and predict the behaviour of her conspecifics by means of reference to hypothetical internal mental states.Baron-Cohens account is desirable of our admiration not just because it describes the current state of scientific play, precisely also because it permits us to generate propositions which, when tested against data, go away refi ne and better our understanding. Neverthe slight, admirable as this attempt at integration of a send of perspectives might be, a reviewer is duty bound to point out unstated assumptions, weaknesses in analysis, un-expressed counter-arguments and problems of interpretation in an authors exposition.To this end I will now try to clarify what I see as the three major areas of weakness in this book. The first concerns Baron-Cohens overall modularist orientation. Although accounts of psychological cognitive process that see behaviour as caused by discrete mental processes that are self-contained, domain-specific, automatic, impenetrable to conscious analysis and localised in specific brain sites has a respectable history, it is not, as its originator, Jerry Fodor would have us believe, the only gimpy in town.It is quite possible to argue that the relationship between the categories we use to analyse behaviour and categories of brain state may be more(prenominal) subtle and more comple x than a simple one-to-one correspondence, and that localisation principle of function may be the result either of anatomical happenstance or may not be a serious contender, given the global and integrated manner in which some neuroscientists think brains work. Readers who might be tempted to call a child SAM-impaired or IDD-but-not-EDD-impaired should read Bates et al. s (1988) critique of modularism, as well as of what she termed in a 1993 bubble thing-in-a-box neurology, before forming such opinions. My second problem with the book concerns the way in which evidence is presented in support of the argument. Baron-Cohen draws on a wide range of evidence to support the four main planks in his argument evolutionary, cognitive, neuropsychological/neurological and cultural. Evolutionary evidence is notoriously difficult to assess, since it inevitably has a post-hoc element to it.This is all the more true of the evolution of behavioural adaptations, since they do not leave fossil rec ords that can allow us to detect non-advantageous changes that have died out. I am also worried by arguments that withhold survival value and evolutionary success on the basis of the widespread use of a particular behaviour. Baron-Cohen attributes the survival of Homo Sapiens to the fact that we have developed mindreading skills. But many other organisms from a-social HIV done bees to the social great apes are evolutionarily successful without mindreading skills.Moreover, I am umbrageous about evolutionary accounts that argue that increasingly complex social organisation in primates led to the development of mind-reading skills. This is as if the behaviours called forth by the survival demands of living in complex societies produced a gene that coded for a brain structure that made a particular social behaviour possible. In my view, there is a worrying circularity about all this, not to mention a whiff of Lamarckianism. On the cognitive front, there is undoubtedly an impressiv e amount of evidence that supports Baron-Cohens case, evidence which he presents cogently and skilfully.Indeed, this is the strongest and virtually closely-argued section of the book. However, there are worrying instances where counter-evidence is either glossed over (e. g. Ozonoff et als, 1991 evidence on the possession of mindreading skills in high-functioning individuals with autism) or relegated to footnotes (Ozonoff et als, 1991 failure to replicate Baron-Cohen et als, 1986 fancy sequencing task). There are other instances where evidence appears to be presented where none exists for example in his preaching of non-autistic peoples use of mental state terms when describing Heider and Simmels (1944) survey sequence.At the time the book was written, no published data existed on the use of this instrument with people with autism (but see Bowler amp Thommen, 1995), although a less than careful reading of this text might lead one to close down that there had been. My third set of reservations centre on often unconformable or imprecise use of terminology. For example, is it justifiable to speak of a module such as ID as interpreting stimuli, quite than just generating output when such stimuli are present and not when they are not?On pp126-127, the discussion slides from psychopathology to neuropathology without explanation. In this section also, I am certain that blind people would not welcome being labelled as having a psychopathology. Examples can also be found of references cited in the text but not in the reference list at the back. All these shortcomings suggest a hasty compilation of the volume. A little more time fatigued on reflection, exposition and the more technical aspects of production would have gainful dividends here.Most of the reservations I have expressed so far all face to stem from the most major problem of this book, namely its length, or rather the mis-match between its length and the aims the author has set himself. Baron-Cohen acknowledges that he faced a difficult task in trying to write for experts in biologic and cognitive sciences, students of psychology and the general reader. Trying to please this four-faceted audience is a difficult enough task it is even more difficult when the debate has to be engaged at several levels of academic discourse. It is well-nigh unrealistic in an essay of about 120 pages of printed text.Its very length constrains the book to contain a little, albeit very important, knowledge. However, a little knowledge can be a very dangerous thing. Although I would recommend this book to anyone with a personal, scientific or clinical interest in autism, to repress danger, I would also recommend that it be consumed with some complementary material. The best I can suggest is a paper by the author himself (Baron-Cohen, 1994), which is accompanied by several commentaries and a reply by the author that gives a better flavour of the subtleties of the field than does the volume under re view here.

No comments:

Post a Comment